The following quotes are extracted from my published paper which deals much more in-depth with the topic at hand, and analyzes each of these texts.
"For if you make change of names a sign of things having been named by
men, you will thereby surely allow that every name has been imposed upon
things by us, since the same appellations of objects have not obtained
universally. For as in the case of Paul who was once Saul, and of Peter who
was formerly Simon, so earth and sky and air and sea and all the parts of the
creation have not been named alike by all, but are named in one way by the
Hebrews, and in another way by us, and are denoted by every nation by
different names. If then Eunomius' argument is valid when he maintains that
it was for this reason, to wit, that their names had been imposed by men, that
Peter and Paul were named afresh, our teaching will surely be valid also,
starting as it does from like premises, which says that all things are named
by us, on the ground that their appellations vary according to the distinctions
of nations. Now if all things are so, surely the Generate and the Ungenerate
are not exceptions, for even they are among the things that change their
name. For when we gather, as it were, into the form of a name the
conception of any subject that arises in us, we declare our concept by words
that vary at different times, not making, but signifying, the thing by the name
we give it. For the things remain in themselves as they naturally are, while
the mind, touching on existing things, reveals its thought by such words as
are available. And just as the essence of Peter was not changed with the change of his name, so neither is any other of the things we contemplate
changed in the process of mutation of names." (Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, book VII, ch. 4)
"For all conceptions and terms which regard the divine are of equal dignity one with another, in that they do not vary in regard to the meaning of the subject matter to which they are applied. Our thought is not led to one subject by the attribution of good, and to another by that of wise, powerful, and just; mention any attributes you will, the thing signified is one and the same. And if you name God, you mean the same Being whom you understood by the rest of the terms. Granting, then, that all the terms applied to the divine nature are of equal force one with another in relation to that which they describe, one emphasizing one point and another another, but all bringing our intelligence to the contemplation of the same object; what ground is there for conceding to the Spirit fellowship with Father and Son in all other terms, and isolating Him from the Godhead alone?" (Basil of Caesarea, Letter 189)
"God, he says, has dominion over His own power. Tell me, what is He? Over
what has He dominion? Is He something else than His own power, and Lord
of a power that is something else than Himself? Then power is overcome by
the absence of power. For that which is something else than power is surely
not power, and thus He is found to have dominion over power just in so far
as He is not power." (Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, Book IX, ch. 1)
"But let us still scrutinize his words. He declares each of these Beings, whom
he has shadowed forth in his exposition, to be single and absolutely one. We
believe that the most boorish and simple-minded would not deny that the
Divine Nature, blessed and transcendent as it is, was 'single.' That which is
viewless, formless, and sizeless, cannot be conceived of as multiform and
composite. But it will be clear, upon the very slightest reflection, that this
view of the supreme Being as 'simple,' however finely they may talk of it, is
quite inconsistent with the system which they have elaborated. For who does
not know that, to be exact, simplicity in the case of the Holy Trinity admits of
no degrees. In this case there is no mixture or conflux of qualities to think
of; we comprehend a potency without parts and composition; how then, and
on what grounds, could any one perceive there any differences of less and
more. For he who marks differences there must perforce think of an
incidence of certain qualities in the subject. He must in fact have perceived
differences in largeness and smallness therein, to have introduced this
conception of quantity into the question: or he must posit abundance or
diminution in the matter of goodness, strength, wisdom, or of anything else
that can with reverence be associated with God: and neither way will he
escape the idea of composition. Nothing which possesses wisdom or power
or any other good, not as an external gift, but rooted in its nature, can suffer diminution in it; so that if any one says that he detects Beings greater and
smaller in the Divine Nature, he is unconsciously establishing a composite
and heterogeneous Deity, and thinking of the Subject as one thing, and the
quality, to share in which constitutes as good that which was not so before,
as another. If he had been thinking of a Being really single and absolutely
one, identical with goodness rather than possessing it, he would not be able
to count a greater and a less in it at all. It was said, moreover, above that
good can be diminished by the presence of evil alone, and that where the
nature is incapable of deteriorating, there is no limit conceived of to the
goodness: the unlimited, in fact, is not such owing to any relation whatever,
but, considered in itself, escapes limitation. It is, indeed, difficult to see how
a reflecting mind can conceive one infinite to be greater or less than another
infinite. So that if he acknowledges the supreme Being to be 'single' and
homogenous, let him grant that it is bound up with this universal attribute of
simplicity and infinitude. If, on the other hand, he divides and estranges the
'Beings' from each other, conceiving that of the Only-begotten as another
than the Father's, and that of the Spirit as another than the Only-begotten,
with a 'more' and 'less' in each case, let him be exposed now as granting
simplicity in appearance only to the Deity, but in reality proving the
composite in Him." (Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, book I, ch. 20)
"Now these modes of generation being well known to men, the loving
dispensation of the Holy Spirit, in delivering to us the Divine mysteries,
conveys its instruction on those matters which transcend language by means
of what is within our capacity, as it does also constantly elsewhere, when it
portrays the Divinity in bodily terms, making mention, in speaking
concerning God, of His eye, His eyelids, His ear, His fingers, His hand, His
right hand, His arm, His feet, His shoes , and the like — none of which
things is apprehended to belong in its primary sense to the Divine Nature,
but turning its teaching to what we can easily perceive, it describes by terms
well-worn in human use, facts that are beyond every name, while by each of
the terms employed concerning God we are led analogically to some more
exalted conception." (Gregory of Nyssa, Against Eunomius, book VIII, ch. 4)
“If you are asked to define the word judge, answer with the interpretation of
ungeneracy; if to define justice, be ready with the incorporeal as your
answer. If asked to define incorruptibility, say that it has the same meaning as mercy or judgment. Thus let all God's attributes be convertible terms,
there being no special signification to distinguish one from another. But if
Eunomius thus prescribes, why do the Scriptures vainly assign various
names to the Divine nature, calling God a Judge, righteous, powerful,
long-suffering, true, merciful and so on? For if none of these titles is to be
understood in any special or peculiar sense, but, owing to this confusion in
their meaning, they are all mixed up together, it would be useless to employ
so many words for the same thing, there being no difference of meaning to
distinguish them from one another. But who is so much out of his wits as not
to know that, while the Divine nature, whatever it is in its essence, is
simple, uniform, and incomposite, and that it cannot be viewed under any
form of complex formation, the human mind, grovelling on earth, and buried
in this life on earth, in its inability to behold clearly the object of its search,
feels after the unutterable Being in various and many-sided ways, and never
chases the mystery in the light of one idea alone. Our grasping of Him would
indeed be easy, if there lay before us one single assigned path to the
knowledge of God: but as it is, from the skill apparent in the Universe, we
get the idea of skill in the Ruler of that Universe, from the large scale of the
wonders worked we get the impression of His Power; and from our belief
that this Universe depends on Him, we get an indication that there is no
cause whatever of His existence; and again, when we see the execrable
character of evil, we grasp His own unalterable pureness as regards this:
when we consider death's dissolution to be the worst of ills, we give the
name of Immortal and Indissoluble at once to Him Who is removed from
every conception of that kind: not that we split up the subject of such
attributes along with them, but believing that this thing we think of,
whatever it be in substance, is One, we still conceive that it has something in
common with all these ideas. For these terms are not set against each other
in the way of opposites, as if, the one existing there, the other could not
co-exist in the same subject (as, for instance, it is impossible that life and
death should be thought of in the same subject); but the force of each of the
terms used in connection with the Divine Being is such that, even though it
has a peculiar significance of its own, it implies no opposition to the term
associated with it. What opposition, for instance, is there between
incorporeal and just, even though the words do not coincide in meaning: and
what hostility is there between goodness and invisibility? So, too, the
eternity of the Divine Life, though represented under the double name and
idea of the unending and the unbeginning, is not cut in two by this difference
of name; nor yet is the one name the same in meaning as the other; the one
points to the absence of beginning, the other to the absence of end, and yet
there is no division produced in the subject by this difference in the actual
terms applied to it. Such is our position.” (Gregory of Nyssa, Answer to Eunomius' Second Book; in NPNF2, 5:298)
"The life, he says, is not a different thing from the substance; no addition
may be thought of in connection with a simple being, by dividing our
conception of him into a communicating and communicated side; but
whatever the life may be, that very thing, he insists, is the substance. Here
his philosophy is excellent; no thinking person would gainsay this." (Gregory of Nyssa, Answer to Eunomius' Second Book; in NPNF2, 5:298)
“He called himself ‘door,’ ‘way,’ ‘bread,’ ‘vine,’ ‘shepherd,’ and ‘light,’ even
though he is not a polyonym. All these names do not carry the same meaning as
one another. For ‘light’ signifies one thing, ‘vine’ another, ‘way’ another, and
‘shepherd’ yet another. Though our Lord is one in substrate, and one substance,
simple and not composite, he calls himself by different names at different times,
using designations that differ from one another for the different conceptualizations.
On the basis of his different activities and his relation to the objects of his divine
benefaction, he employs different names for himself….If anyone should examine
each of the names one by one, he would find the various conceptualizations, even
though for all there is one substrate as far as substance is concerned." (Basil of Caesarea, Contra Eunomium, 1.7)
"The Father, the Son and the Holy Ghost alike hallow, quicken, enlighten, and
comfort. No one will attribute a special and peculiar operation of hallowing
to the operation of the Spirit, after hearing the Saviour in the Gospel saying
to the Father about His disciples, sanctify them in Your name [John 17:17?].
In like manner all other operations are equally performed, in all who are
worthy of them, by the Father and by the Son and by the Holy Ghost; every
grace and virtue, guidance, life, consolation, change into the immortal, the
passage into freedom and all other good things which come down to
man….Identity of operation in the case of Father and of Son and of Holy
Ghost clearly proves invariability of nature." (Basil of Caesarea, Letter 189; in NPNF2: 8:231)
“Moreover, in response to the objection that God will be revealed as composite
unless the light is understood as the same thing as ingeneracy, we have the
following to say: if we should understand ingeneracy as part of the substance, then
there would be room for the argument which claims that what is compounded from
different things is composite. But if we should posit, on the one hand, the light, or
the life, or the good as the substance of God, claiming that the very thing which
God is is life as a whole, light as a whole, and good as a whole, while, on the other
hand, we should posit that the life has ingeneracy as a concomitant, then how is the
one who is simple in substance not incomposite? For surely the ways of indicating
his proprium will not violate the account of simplicity.” (Basil of Caesarea, Contra Eunomium, 2.29)
"Now, if [the Holy Spirit] is divine, then certainly it is also good, powerful,
wise, glorious, eternal, and all such names that lift our thoughts to a level
appropriate to its grandeur. The simplicity of the subject ensures that it does
not possess these names by participation (ἐκ μετουσίας), as if one could
suppose that it is one thing in its own nature, but becomes something
different through the presence of the aforementioned names. Such a situation
is proper to those beings that have a composite nature. But all people equally
confess that the Holy Spirit is simple; there is no one who would dispute it. So then, if the formula (λόγος) of its nature is simple, it does not possess
goodness as something acquired (ἐπίκτητον). Rather, the very thing it is
(αὐτὸ ὅ τι ποτέ ἐστιν), is goodness, wisdom, power, holiness, justice,
eternity, incorruptibility, and all the names that are sublime and elevating." (Gregory of Nyssa, Against the Macedonians, §5)
No comments:
Post a Comment